Human language may seem majestic, from the perspective of a vervet monkey confined to a vocabulary of three words (roughly,
The challenge, for the cognitive scientist, is to figure out which idiosyncrasies are really important. Most are mere trivia, amusing but not reflective of the deep structures of the mind. The word
*If to err is human, to write it down is divine. This chapter is written in memory of the late Vicki Fromkin, an early pioneer in linguistics who was the first to systematically collect and study human speech errors. You can read more about her at
http:// www.linguistics.ucla.edu/people/fromkin/fromkin.htm.for example, used to refer to driving on a private road that went from a main road to a house. In truth, we still drive on (or at least into) driveways, but we scarcely notice the
Likewise it is amusing but not deeply significant to note that we "relieve" ourselves in water closets and bathrooms, even though our W.C.'s are bigger than closets and our bathrooms have no baths. (For that matter, public restrooms may be public, and may be rooms, but I've never seen anyone rest in one.) But our reluctance to say where we plan to go when we "have to go" isn't really a flaw in language; it's just a circumlocution, a way of talking around the details in order to be polite.
Some of the most interesting linguistic quirks, however, run deeper, reflecting not just the historical accidents of particular languages, but fundamental truths about those creatures that produce language — namely, us.
Consider, for instance, the fact that
To be perfect, a language would presumably have to be unambiguous (except perhaps where deliberately intended to be ambiguous), sys
Language
tematic (rather than idiosyncratic), stable (so that, say, grandparents could communicate with their grandchildren), nonredundant (so as not to waste time or energy), and capable of expressing any and all of our thoughts.* Every instance of a given speech sound would invariably be pronounced in a constant way, each sentence as clean as a mathematical formula. In the words of one of the leading philosophers of the twentieth century, Bertrand Russell,
in a logically perfect language, there will be one word and no more for every simple object, and everything that is not simple will be expressed by a combination of words, by a combination derived, of course, from the words for the simple things that enter in, one word for each simple component. A language of that sort will be completely analytic, and will show at a glance the logical structure of the facts asserted or denied.