I understand how strange such an abstract theoretical wringing process, full of allusions and terms unfamiliar to the Western ear, must seem. Moreover, it may turn out that in proposing a system of categories forjudging political structures, I have, as they say, reinvented the wheel. I understand all this. But I can do nothing about it: otherwise my encounter with the reader is in danger of becoming yet another dialogue of the deaf.
The first part of this book is of necessity theoretical, since it is designed to acquaint the reader with my conception of the origin and nature of the Russian political structure. In this part I seek:
To give as precise as possible a description of "despotism" and "absolutism";
To give a description of "Russian autocracy";
To demonstrate that prior historiography known to me proceeds almost entirely from the bipolar model of political classification;
To show that, precisely for this reason, it is incapable of adequately describing the origin and nature of the Russian political structure.
It goes without saying that most Soviet authors reject with an offended air the very possibility that Russia might belong in the category of Asiatic despotism, and decidedly count it in the family of European absolutism, while most Western authors who are sensitive to theoretical issues are convinced of the opposite. For this reason, I will call the first, for brevity's sake, "absolutists," and the latter "despotists."
This chapter will be devoted to definitions. In chapter two, I will try to show how it comes about that the "absolutists" are unable to explain the origin and nature of the Russian political process. The third chapter will be devoted to the "despotists."
Aristotle knew that in addition to the three regular and three irregular ("deviant") forms of political organization characteristic of the civilized
The human mind is not capable of understanding how a people can tolerate tyranny on a permanent basis. For this reason Aristotle saw in despotism something inhuman. And this is not surprising if we remember that "barbarism" was, for him, only the external political dimension of the internal political condition of "slavery." Neither the slave nor the barbarian (the potential slave) could be considered a human being, since the first mark of a human being was, for Aristotle, participation in courts and councils—that is, in the administration of society. Man, for him, was a political animal. This, properly speaking, makes it understandable why he could not consider despotism as a political structure at all.
But Aristotle nevertheless does introduce a certain original element into what I would call the science of despotology. In fact, if we try to look at his theory of "deviations" from a modern point of view, we see immediately that he has in mind the problem of divergence between the goals of the social